Monday, September 10, 2012

Every Functor is a (Co)Reflection

Every Functor is a (Co)Reflection:


MathML-enabled post (click for more details).


Recall that a reflection is a left adjoint to the inclusion of a full subcategory, and a coreflection is a right adjoint to such an inclusion. Of course, it is not literally true that every functor is a (co)reflection! However, it is true that every functor can be made into a (co)relection by changing its domain. More precisely, we can prove:

Theorem: Let F:C→D be any functor. Then there exists a category E, which contains C as a full subcategory and D as a full reflective subcategory, such that when the reflector is restricted to C it agrees with F.

You might try thinking about how to prove this; I’ll give an answer below the fold.


MathML-enabled post (click for more details).


Proof: Let E be the collage of the corepresented profunctor D(F,1). That is, the objects of E are the disjoint union of the objects of C and D, with

E(x,y) =C(x,y) if x,y∈C E(x,y) =D(x,y) if x,y∈D E(x,y) =D(Fx,y) if ;x∈C and y∈D E(x,y) =∅ if x∈D and y∈C.

It’s easy to define the composition in E, and to see that it satisfies the conclusion of the theorem. □

Of course, using the dual profunctor D(1,F) produces a dual version of the theorem where F becomes a coreflection.

As usual with this sort of thing, the construction in the theorem is not very enlightening. The category E is so cooked up that it can’t possibly give us any new insight about F. But in the spirit of Lack’s coherence theorem (“naturally occurring bicategories are equivalent to naturally occurring 2-categories”), we can still use the idea of this theorem in a useful way. Namely, it may happen for a particular functor F that there is some naturally occurring category E which satisfies the conclusion of the theorem. If so, this can give us a new way to understand F.

I have two examples of this in mind at the moment (but I’m hoping that people will be able to suggest others in the comments). The first is my exact completions paper. This is actually a categorified example, where C is the 2-category of categories with weak finite limits, D is the 2-category of exact categories, and F is the free exact completion. When the domain of F is restricted to categories with actual finite limits, then it becomes an adjoint to the forgetful functor from exact categories to finitely complete categories. However, this is not the case in general.

What was known before my paper is that there’s a profunctor H, other than D(F,1), whose collage we can use in the above proof of the theorem. Of course, this implies that H must be isomorphic to D(F,1), but the point is that H is not defined to be D(F,1); in fact, its definition doesn’t refer to F at all. Specifically, if X has weak finite limits and Y is exact, then H(X,Y) is a the full subcategory of Cat(X,Y) whose objects are “left covering” functors. (The definition of left covering functor is irrelevant to this post, so I will omit it.)

This is interesting and somewhat useful — it means that F does have some sort of universal property — but still somewhat mysterious. What I managed to do was find a naturally occurring 2-category E, not the collage of any profunctor, for which the conclusion of the theorem holds. Namely, E is the 2-category of unary sites. It so happens that if X has weak finite limits and we give it the trivial topology, and Y is exact and we give it its regular topology, then E(X,Y) is precisely the category of left covering functors from X to Y. Thus we recover the previously known universal property, but we also learn a good deal more.

The reason I was inspired to write this post is that I recently learned of another such “naturally occurring” instance of this theorem. Let C be the category of uniform spaces, D the category of topological spaces, and F the functor which associates to a uniformity its underlying topology. The functor F has a left adjoint, but this doesn’t tell us much about F beyond that it preseves limits; the only definition I know of for the adjoint is very adjoint-functor-theorem-y (given a topology τ on X, give X the finest uniformity whose underlying topology is coarser than τ).

However, there is a “naturally occurring” category E which contains C and D as full subcategories, in which D is coreflective, and such that the coreflector becomes F when restricted to C. This category E consists of syntopogenous spaces. (That’s quite a mouthful!) The idea is:


  • A topogenous relation on a set X is a relation of “nearness” between pairs of subsets of X.

  • A syntopogenous structure on X is a suitable collection of topogenous relations.



If X is a topological space, then we define a topogenous relation on X by saying that A is near to B if A contains a point of the closure of B. (Note that this is not a symmetric relation.) This relation clearly contains all the information of the topology of X. The syntopogenous structure on X generated by this single relation yields the embedding of topological spaces into syntopogenous ones.

On the other hand, if X is a uniform space, then every entourage U of X yields a topogenous relation, where A is near to B if there are points x∈A and y∈B which are U-close. The collection of these relations, as U ranges over the entourages of X, generates a syntopogenous structure on X which yield the embedding of uniform spaces into syntopogenous ones.

One can characterize which syntopogenous structures arise from topologies, which arise from uniformities, and also which arise from proximities. It turns out that the topological ones are coreflective, and the coreflection computes the underlying topology of a uniformity, and also of a proximity. You can read more at the nLab page syntopogenous space, and in the reference cited therein (Ákos Császár, Foundations of General Topology).

I don’t claim that syntopogenous spaces are useful for anything. (Although I’d be amused to be proven wrong.) But it’s fun to discover new universal properties for familiar functors. Can anyone think of any other examples?

One thing that these two examples have in common, which I find interesting, is that in both cases we are used to thinking of the objects of D as objects of C with extra structure (or properties). However, inside of E, the images of C and D are almost disjoint. An exact category with its regular topology, and with its trivial topology, are almost always different unary sites. And the only syntopogenous structures that are both topological and uniform are just sets equipped with equivalence relations. (And of course, in the collage of D(F,1), the images of C and D are literally disjoint.) There’s no other way the theorem could be true, of course, but I think it points out in a new way the relativity of the notion of “extra structure”.



DIGITAL JUICE

No comments:

Post a Comment

Thank's!